CLASS-FEELING IN EDUCATION
CLASS-FEELING IN EDUCATION
(Bertrand Russell)
Ever since
the dawn of civilisation, class inequality has existed. Among savage tribes at
the present day, it takes very simple forms. There are chiefs, and the chiefs
are able to have several wives. Savages, unlike civilised men, have found a way
of making wives a source of wealth, so that the more wives a man has the
wealthier he becomes. But this primitive form of social inequality soon gave
way to others more complex. In the main, social inequality has been bound up
with inheritance, and therefore, in all patriarchal societies, with descent in
the male line. Originally, the greater wealth of certain persons was due to
military prowess. The successful fighter
acquired wealth, and transmitted it to his sons. Wealth acquired by the sword
usually consisted of land, and to this day land-owning is the mark of the
aristocrat, the aristocrat being in theory the descendant of some feudal baron,
who acquired his lands by killing the previous occupant and holding his
acquisition against all comers. This is considered the most honourable source
of wealth. There are others slightly less honourable, exemplified
by those who, while completely idle themselves, have acquired their wealth by
inheritance from an ndustrious ancestor; and yet others, still less
respectable, whose wealth is due to their own industry. In the modern world,
the plutocrat who, though rich, still works, is gradually ousting the
aristocrat, whose income was in theory derived solely from ownership of land
and natural monopolies. There have been two main legal sources of property:
one, the aristocratic source, namely, ownership of land; the other, the
bourgeois source, namely, the right to the produce of one’s own labour. The
right to the produce of one’s own labour has always existed only on paper, because
things are made out of other things, and the man who supplies the raw material
exacts a right to the finished
product in return for wages, or, where slavery exists, in return for the bare
necessaries of life. We have thus three orders of men – the land-owner, the
capitalist, and the proletarian. The capitalist in origin is merely a man whose
savings have enabled him to buy the raw materials and the tools required in
manufacturing, and who has thereby acquired the right to the finished
product in return for wages. The three categories of land-owner, capitalist,
and proletarian are clear enough in theory; but in practice the distinctions
are blurred. A land-owner may employ business methods in developing a seaside
resort which happens to be upon his property. A capitalist whose money is
derived from manufacture may invest the whole or part of his fortune in land,
and take to living upon rent. A proletarian, in so far as he has money in the
savings bank, or a house which he is buying on the instalment plan, becomes to
that extent a capitalist or a landowner as the case may be. The eminent
barrister who charges a thousand guineas for a brief should, in strict
economics, be classified as a
proletarian. But he would be indignant if this were done, and has the mentality
of a plutocrat.
From a
practical point of view, the important class distinctions outside the
depend upon the patriarchal family and the practice of inheritance.
Owing to the patriarchal family, the children of the rich get a different
education, though not always a better one, than is given to the children of the
poor. Owing to inheritance, the children of the rich may look forward, if they
so desire, to idleness without starvation. If there were no such thing as
inheritance, the inequalities of wealth which would survive would be
obliterated in each generation. And if there were no such thing as the
patriarchal family, the children of the rich would not be educated differently
from the children of the poor. Socialists are apt to speak of the capitalist
system in a somewhat vague way, without an adequate analysis of the different
factors which contribute to it. The business activities of the capitalist are
by no means the whole of the capitalist system. The fact that his children are
in a privileged position owing to his wealth is an essential part of it. I do
not mean this as a criticism of Marxism, since Marx realised the connection
between economics and the family. But I do say it in criticism of a good many
English-speaking Socialists, who imagine that the economic structure of society
has no very vital connection with marriage and the family. As a matter of fact,
the connection is reciprocal. The bourgeois who is concerned in amassing
private property applies the conception of private property to his wife and
children, and has in consequence a certain way of feeling in regard to them.
Conversely, sexual jealousy and paternal affection
are emotions leading men to desire private property in women and children. And
from their desire for this form of private property they are led to desire
other forms also. In a primitive community, a man may desire wealth in order to
have many wives. In a civilised community, one of the reasons for desiring
wealth is to be able to give a better social status to one’s wife and children
than belongs to the wives and children of wage-earners. The connection of
private property in material things with private property in women and children
is thus reciprocal. It cannot be expected that one will break down without the other
also breaking down. Private property in women and children introduces rivalry
in regard to them, and thus brings the motive of class distinction into
education. How all these matters would be affected
by a thoroughgoing communism I do not propose to consider at this stage.
Where
education is concerned it is, of course, the social position of the fathers
that determines that of the children. Thus in any society in which class
distinctions exist, children are respected not solely on account of their own merits,
but also on account of the wealth of their fathers. The children of the rich
acquire a belief that they are superior to the children of the poor, and an
attempt is made to cause the children of the poor to think themselves inferior
to the children of the rich. It is necessary to make this effort
with the children of the poor, since otherwise they might come to resent the
injustice of which they are the victims. Consequently, wherever class
distinctions exist, education necessarily has two correlative defects: that of
producing arrogance in the rich, and that of aiming at irrational humility in
the poor. The objections to the arrogance of the rich are obvious, and have
been pointed out by the moralist from the time of the Hebrew prophets
downwards, though only a small percentage of the moralists have noticed that
the evil could not be undone by mere preaching, but only by a different
economic system. The evils of attempting to produce irrational humility in the
poor are somewhat different. If it
is produced, initiative and self-respect are harmfully diminished. If it is not
produced, there is resentment tending to destructiveness. Whether it is
produced or whether it is not, the attempt to produce it involves the teaching
of falsehood: ethical falsehood, since it is a representation that the
inequality of the rich and the poor is not an injustice; economic falsehood,
since it is suggested that the present economic system is the best possible;
historical falsehood, since the previous conflicts
of rich and poor are narrated from the standpoint of the rich. When the
teachers are little better than proletarians themselves, they need slavish
souls if they are to believe what they have to teach, and lack of courage if
they are to teach it without believing it.
In
pre-industrial societies, where wealth is mainly aristocratic, the defence of
inequality takes the form of reverence for birth, which often overrides the
reverence for actual wealth, and conceals the economic origin of the sentiment.
A penniless exiled chieftain may be more respected than a successful
money-lender. Nevertheless, fundamentally it is wealth that is respected,
because as a rule in such societies it is aristocratic descent which is the
source of wealth. Where aristocracy is strong, belief in it is, of course,
bolstered up by all kinds of nonsense, such as that aristocrats have better
manners, more education, or finer feelings
than other people. In a plutocratic society, such as that of the United States,
there is a different form
of humbug. The successful plutocrat is supposed to have achieved his position
by hard work, frugality, and scrupulous honesty. He is supposed to use his
position as a public trust, with an eye always to the general good. In the
sixties and seventies of the last century, when the great fortunes of
plutocrats were a novelty, traditional culture, such as that of the Adams
family, exposed with gusto the tricks and chicanery and sheer illegality by
which many of the leading men had amassed their wealth.1
Throughout the eighties and nineties, books were written against the
methods of the Standard Oil Company. Nowadays, this is all changed. The great
plutocrats are regarded as great public benefactors. Every university has, or
hopes to have, endowments from them. Every young man of academic tastes hopes
to receive a research fellowship from the bounty of some philanthropic
billionaire. The universities and the press are filled
with the praise of the very rich, and the man in the street is taught to
believe that virtue is proportional to income. Class distinctions are thus just
as important in a country like the United States as they are in an aristocratic
country, and a good deal more important than they are in countries such as
Norway and Denmark, where there is diffused
comfort with hardly any great fortunes.
The harm
done by class distinctions is not confined
to the children. It extends to the teachers and the curriculum. More social
prestige attaches to care of the mind than to care of the body, and therefore
the teacher who gives intellectual instruction is usually indifferent
to questions of health, and ignorant of the signs by which the first
approaches of any physical ailment can be detected. The distinction between
mind and body is artificial and
unreal; but unfortunately it has had an effect
upon the social hierarchy, with the result that care of the body and care of
the mind are much more separated in education than they ought to be. This, of
course, is nothing like as bad as it was in former days, when a deaf child
might be punished for inattention for years on end without any of the teachers
discovering that he was deaf. But although such extreme instances as this are
not likely to occur nowadays, the evil still exists in less flagrant
forms. The teacher, for example, knows nothing about the child’s digestive
condition, and may be indignant at stupidity and bad temper for which the cause
is to be found in constipation. If it were suggested to teachers that they
should pay any attention to the bowel action of their pupils, their snobbery
would be outraged. I do not wish the reader to misunderstand me at this point.
I am not denying that in all modern schools there is physical care of children,
and that a great deal is done to keep them in health, as compared with what used
to be done in former times. What I am complaining of is that physical and
mental care are so completely separated, and that the person who possesses the
knowledge required for the one has, as a rule, no inkling of the knowledge
required for the other. In an adult there is a considerable gulf between mind
and body, but this gulf has no metaphysical necessity. It is a produce of
education. In a baby there is no gulf, in an infant there is very little, and
in a child not much. I do not suppose that a child of ten could give a very
good philosophical account of the difference
between mind and body. But every child would understand at once if you said:
‘Your mind is what is looked after by Miss A., and your body is what is looked
after by Miss B.’ It is the distinction between Miss A. and Miss B. that
underlies the subsequent metaphysical distinction between mind and matter. If
the functions of Miss A. and Miss B. were combined in a Miss C., all children
would grow up to be neutral monists, believing that mind and matter are only different
aspects of the same phenomenon. In this way, metaphysics is connected with the
class system. Mental activity is that which does not involve the use of arms or
legs. Physical activity is that which does. Mental activity is superior to
physical, because those who practice it exclusively need servants to do their
physical labours for them. It follows that the soul is nobler than the body,
that matter is the evil principle, and so on.
As regards
the curriculum also, respect for wealth has had an effect,
though this effect is less
obvious than formerly. The Greeks, like all communities that employ slave
labour, held the view that all manual work is vulgar. This led them to place a
great emphasis upon such things as culture and philosophy and rhetoric, which
could be studied without the use of the hands. They tended to think that all
manipulation of matter was unworthy of a gentleman, and this probably had
something to do with their partial lack of success in experimental science.
Plutarch, relating the ingenious inventions of Archimedes during the siege of
Syracuse, defends him from the charge of vulgarity on the ground that he was
doing it for the benefit of his
cousin the King. The Romans inherited the Greek view of culture, and down to
our own day this view has been dominant in all countries of Western Europe.
Culture is something which can be acquired by reading books, or by
conversation. Whatever involves more than this is not culture in the Greek
meaning of the term. And the Greek education
and the social order meaning of the term is still that adopted, at
any rate in England, by most schoolmasters, many university teachers, and all
old gentlemen with literary tastes. This applies not only to Greek and Roman
antiquity, but also to modern history. It is considered more cultured to know
about Horace Walpole than about Henry Cavendish, about Bolingbroke than about
Robert Boyle, though in each case the latter was the more important man. All
this is ultimately connected with the idea that a gentleman is one who does not
use his hands unless it be in the noble art of war. A gentleman may use a
sword, but should not use a typewriter.
In matters
of this sort, the United States is much ahead of Europe, owing to the fact
that, in America, aristocracy was abolished with emphasis at a time when it
still existed in every
European
country. But a new form of class distinction in education is growing up, which
is the distinction between business management and the technical processes of
manufacture. The man engaged in business management is the aristocrat of the
future, and the phrase ‘a great executive’ has much the same connotations in
modern America that the phrase ‘a great nobleman’ had in the novels of
Disraeli. The substitution of the great executive for the great nobleman as the
type to be admired is having a considerable effect
upon ideals of culture. A great nobleman, in the dithyrambic day-dreams of
Disraeli, was, no doubt, a man possessed of power, but it was power which had
come to him without his having had to seek it, and which he exercised somewhat
lazily. He was possessed also of great wealth, but this, again, had come to him
without exertion, and he affected to
think little of it. The things upon which he prided himself were his exquisite manners,
his knowledge of good wine, his familiarity with the great world of all
civilised countries, his judgement in regard to Renaissance pictures, and his
capacity for epigram. It may be said generally that the accomplishments of
aristocrats were frivolous, but innocent. The accomplishments of the great
executives of our own time are very different.
They class-feeling in education are
men whose position has been achieved by their powerful will, and their capacity
for judging other men. Power is their ruling passion, organising is the
activity in which they excel.
They are men
capable of doing the greatest good or the greatest harm, men who must be
respected for their abilities and their importance, and loved or hated
according to the nature of their work, but never viewed with indifference
or condescension. In an industrial world men of this type must come to the
fore. In the USSR men of this type are utilised by the State in ways which give
scope for their abilities, without permitting the ruthless individualism of
which they are allowed to be guilty in the capitalist world. But whether under
capitalism or under communism, it is men of this type who must ultimately
dominate an industrial civilisation, and the difference
between their mentality and that of aristocrats of former times must have an
important influence in
making industrial culture different from
that of feudal and commercial ages.
The
conception of ‘the education of a gentleman’ has had a bad effect
upon universities. Young people who are not exceptionally intellectual find
it difficult in the years between eighteen and
twenty-two to take very seriously the acquisition of academic knowledge, which
is going to be of no direct use to them in later life. They tend, therefore, to
be idle at the university, or if they work, to do so from mere thoughtless
conscientiousness. For those whose profession is going to be research, the
universities are admirable, but for most of the rest they are too much out of
touch with subsequent life. It is possible to spend the university years in the
acquisition of knowledge which has some professional utility, but conservative
academic types view this with horror. I think they are mistaken. I think many
clever young men become vapid and cynical through the consciousness that their
work has no real importance while they are at the university. This does not
happen to those who are studying medicine or engineering or agriculture or any
subject of which education and the social
order the utility is obvious. A gentleman is intended to be ornamental
rather than useful, but in order to be adequately ornamental he has to be
supplied with an unearned income. For those who will have to earn their living,
it is hardly wise to attempt a form of education whose main purpose was to make
idleness elegant. Pure learning as an ideal has its place in the life of the
community, but only for those few who are going to devote their energies to
research. For those who are going to be engaged in some other profession, it
would be better to spend the last years of education in acquiring such
knowledge as would enable them to pursue their profession with intelligence and
breadth of outlook. There is no such thing nowadays as an all-round education,
but there is a tendency, especially in England, to over-emphasise those
elements in education which enable a man to talk with seeming intelligence.
Moreover, knowledge acquired at the university, if it is quite unrelated to
subsequent professional work, is likely to be soon forgotten. If professional men
of forty were examined in the subjects that they had studied at the university,
I am afraid it would be found that in most cases very little knowledge
remained. Whereas, if they had studied something which enabled them to see
their profession in relation to the life of the community, and to understand
its social aspects, it is likely that their subsequent experiences would have
supplied illustrations to what they had learned, and would therefore have
caused the knowledge to remain in their minds.
I have dealt
hitherto with incidental disadvantages derived from class-distinctions, but I
have only touched upon the greatest disadvantage, which is ethical. Wherever
unjust inequalities exist, a man who profits
by them tends to protect himself from a sense of guilt by theories suggesting
that he is in some way better than those who are less fortunate. These theories
involve a limitation of sympathy, and opposition to justice, and a tendency to
defend the status quo. They thus
make the more fortunate members of the community into opponents of all
progress; fear invades class-feeling
in education their souls, and they shrink timidly from all
doctrines that they suspect of having a subversive tendency, and of being
therefore a threat to their own comfort. On the other hand, the less fortunate
members of the community must either suffer
such intellectual atrophy that they do not perceive the injustice of which they
are the victims, and such moral loss of self-respect that they are willing to
bow down before men intrinsically no better than themselves, or they must be filled
with anger and resentment, protesting indignantly, feeling a continual sense of
grievance, and gradually coming to view the world through the jaundiced eyes of
the victim of persecution mania. All tolerated injustice has thus two bad
sides: one as regards the fortunate, and the other as regards the unfortunate.
It is for these reasons rather than from any abstract excellence in justice for
its own sake that unjust social systems are evil. In a community based upon
injustice, the ethical side of education can never be what it should be.
Emotions of resentment which, considered in themselves, are bad, may be a very
necessary motive force in eliminating injustice, whether between classes,
nations, or sexes. But they do not cease to be intrinsically undesirable by
being politically necessary. And it should be a touch-stone of the good society
that, in it, the usual emotions will be those that are kindly, friendly, and
constructive, rather than those that are angry and destructive. This
consideration, if followed out, will lead us very far. But as our theme is
education, I will leave it to the reader to carry the argument to its
conclusion.
Wow Nyc Post Also Check out This
ReplyDeleteHassan Khokhar
Apps reviews
Fancy text
PkOnlineClasses
Visit Here I hope you enjoy It
Wow Nyc Post Also Check out This
Hassan Khokhar
Apps reviews
Fancy text
PkOnlineClasses
Visit Here I hope you enjoy It
Wow Nyc Post Also Check out This
Hassan Khokhar
Apps reviews
Fancy text
PkOnlineClasses
Visit Here I hope you enjoy It
Wow Nyc Post Also Check out This
Hassan Khokhar
Apps reviews
Fancy text
PkOnlineClasses
Visit Here I hope you enjoy It
Wow Nyc Post Also Check out This
Hassan Khokhar
Apps reviews
Fancy text
PkOnlineClasses
Visit Here I hope you enjoy It
Wow Nyc Post Also Check out This
Hassan Khokhar
Apps reviews
Fancy text
PkOnlineClasses
Visit Here I hope you enjoy It
Wow Nyc Post Also Check out This
Hassan Khokhar
Apps reviews
Fancy text
PkOnlineClasses
Visit Here I hope you enjoy It
Wow Nyc Post Also Check out This
Hassan Khokhar
Apps reviews
Fancy text
PkOnlineClasses
Visit Here I hope you enjoy It